Suppose we are are the hiring committee for econ department. These are 3 candidates and the commitee consists of 3 people.. only one candidate will be selected, so there are three possible outcomes. Each committee member has complete and transitive preferences over candidates.
Key words: completeness and transitive.
Completeness: for all
, we have that or (or both). Transitivity: For all
, if and , then .
Given individual preferences, we would like to find the unique preference of the committee, the procedure turning members' preference is called social choice function
Let's define the model now
Finite set of alternatives
Finite set of individuals
Each individual has complete and transivitive preference
The social choice function is
, where
and we use
Examples of social choice functions
Ignoring individual preferences:
The majority rule:
say
and are two alternatives, Let's say 3 committees 1,2,3, their rankings are
1:
2:
3:
What is the social choice function?
Consider A vs B, 2 committees vote A over B but only one vote B over A, so
. Similarly, we can find
and So this social choice function is not transivitive.
Dictatorship(独裁)
Arrow's Axioms
Unrestricted domain:
The social choice function
Does majority rule satisfies the axiom?
No, because it does not give us an outcome in the domain.
Weak Pareto principle (unonimity, 一致同意 everyone agrees)
if
Does These three above examples satisfies this axiom?
Dictator: Yes. Because if everyone including the dictator agrees, then it becomes the soical choice
Majority: Yes Because if everyone agrees, it becomes majority, then it becomes the soical choice
Ignoring? No because everyone agrees does not necessarily imply the social choice agreement.
Independence of irrelevant alternatives
Let
If every individual rank
如果在两种不同的规则下每个人都有同样的排序,那么这两种规则下的social choice也一致
No dictatorship
There is no individual
Borda Count
Let
Each alternatives "counts" is the sum of each individuals rank
Example
4 people, and 4 alternatives
Ranking the best city in USA,
1 2 3 4 NYC LA R M LA NYC NYC LA M M M R R R LA NYC Here counts:
NYC: 9, LA: 9 Miami:10 Raleigh: 12
then we conclude:
But if we changes the third individual's ranking on NYC- R - M - LA
Then counts changes to NYC: 8, LA: 9, Miami: 10, Raleign: 13
Then we conclude becomes
But what we find from this example? It violates the independence of irrelevant assumption
Because the third individual does not change his preference between LA and NYC, but the final ranking changes.
Theorem
Let
Homework for Tuesday
Show that Borda Count satisfies all other axioms
Suppose the Borda Count violates Unrestrictive domain axiom, which means we are unable to generate any social preference between
and , in other words, we are unable to compare the counts on and . However, we know that counts on and always satifies one of the following relation: , which implies that there must be one of the following to be true:
This is the proof of completeness.
Tand suppose
, and , which implies the count on . That proved the transitivity. Overall
is well defined over .
For Weak Pareto principle. Let's say for each individual
, we have , which implies that for all , we have count on count on . Therefore, if we sum all the counts across
, then , which implies that
.
For No dictatorship principle. Suppose we have a dictator
whose preference is , i.e. 's counts on counts on . Then based on this axiom, no matther what the others' preference are, the social choice function is . Now, consider an extreme case that all other and , such that and the sum of counts on counts on . Hence, according to the rule of Borda count, , which contradicts to the social preference based on dictator. Therefore, the Borda count satisfies all other 3 axioms.
When
, show Borda count satisfies all 4 axioms From the previous question, we have already shown the Borda count satifies axiom of U, WP, and ND.
So let's consider the IIA when
. Let
and and . And every individual rank and the same way under and . Since we only have two alternatives and , so for all . Then the social choice rank and the same way under and as well because . IIA also satisfies when
.
Now let's rigorously prove the theorem.
Proof
Step 1:
Let
, be the lowest preferred alternative for all . By Unrestricted domain, Social welfare function chooses a social preference for
, i.e. , (There exists a social choice ) By Weak pareto principle,
is ranked of the bottom under social choice .
... Step 2:
Now, let's do one-by-one, remove
from the bottom of the ranking of each individual to the top, is well defined under such new ranking profile due to unrestricted domain, and by weak pareto, is ranked at the top of the new social ranking .
... So at some point, let's say at individual
, after changing the ranking of individual , becomes the top of the social choice (social ranking). Claim: There exist
such that moves from the bottom to top when we change 's ranking. We can also prove this Claim:
On the controry of some step
move up in the social ranking but not to the top, say one new social choice such that . Then at that step is either ranked at the bottom or at the top by all individuals. Then without changing the relative ranking, compared to
, we rank over for all individuals. say this new social ranking . According to WP,
According to IIA,
and nobody has changed relative ranking between and , so under new social ranking, , and similarly, . By transversality, , contradiction! Step 3:
Let
and be any two alternatives, consider the profile in which we change the first individuals. Consider and change her ranking as , (under ). In the new profile
is ranked over under the social ranking (IIA), , and from t6his intermediate profile and the one all first individuals ranking at the top, the relative ranking of and the same, Then IIA gives . Then by transversality we have . Notice that independent of the rankings of the other individuals for
and , the social ranking agrees with 's ranking over and . Since
and are any arbitrary two alternatives, social ranking mimics the ranking of for any two alternatives that we choose from . That indicates that is a dictator!